Abstract
Loophole-free violations of Bell inequalities imply that at least one of the assumptions behind local hidden-variable theories must fail. Here, we show that, if only one fails, then it has to fail completely, therefore excluding models that partially constrain freedom of choice or allow for partial retrocausal influences, or allow partial instantaneous actions at a distance. Specifically, we show that (i) any hidden-variable theory with outcome independence (OI) and arbitrary joint relaxation of measurement independence (MI) and parameter independence (PI) can be experimentally excluded in a Bell-like experiment with many settings on high-dimensional entangled states, and (ii) any hidden-variable theory with MI, PI and arbitrary relaxation of OI can be excluded in a Bell-like experiment with many settings on qubit-qubit entangled states.
Similar content being viewed by others
Introduction
In the early days of quantum theory, the question of whether there is deeper theory underlying quantum theory was considered “a philosophical question for which physical arguments alone are not decisive”1. Bell’s theorem2,3 made it possible to exclude experimentally some of these deeper theories, called hidden-variable (HV) theories4. Today, Bell tests5,6,7,8,9 have convinced us that some HV theories cannot explain what we see.
In a Bell test, a source of pairs of particles sends each particle to a different laboratory. In the first laboratory, an observer (Alice) chooses to measure x ∈ X and obtains a ∈ A. In the second laboratory, a different observer (Bob) chooses to measure y ∈ Y and obtains b ∈ B. After many repetitions, Alice and Bob compute the joint probability of (a, b) given (x, y), denoted p(a, b∣x, y). The set {p(a, b∣x, y)}x∈X,y∈Y,a∈A,b∈B is called a correlation for the Bell scenario (∣X∣, ∣A∣; ∣Y∣, ∣B∣), in which Alice can choose between ∣X∣ measurement settings with ∣A∣ possible outcomes and Bob between ∣Y∣ settings with ∣B∣ outcomes.
Bell’s theorem asserts that no HV model satisfying some assumptions can reproduce certain quantum correlations. These models are collectively called “local” HV models and are defined as those satisfying the following assumptions10,11:
(0) Hidden variables. There are hidden variables that associate to each pair of particles a state λ ∈ Λ and underlying probability densities p(a, b∣λ, x, y) and p(λ∣x, y) so
(1) Measurement independence (MI): For every pair of particles, the measurements (x, y) are not correlated with λ. That is, p(x, y∣λ) = p(x, y), which, through Bayes’s theorem, is equivalent to
Therefore, the knowledge of λ gives no information about (x, y), and vice versa.
(2) Outcome independence (OI)11 also referred to as completeness10,12: p(a∣λ, x, y, b) is independent of b, and hence may be written
Similarly, p(b∣λ, x, y, a) = p(b∣λ, x, y).
(3) Parameter independence (PI)11, initially called locality10: p(a∣λ, x, y) is independent of y, and hence may be written as
Similarly, p(b∣λ, x, y) = p(b∣λ, y).
Assumptions (2) and (3) are independent10 and, together, imply that
which is Bell’s original assumption2 which is now called local factorizability or local causality.
Assumption (0) is the expression of the belief in a deeper theory underlying quantum theory. MI is motivated by the assumption that each of the observers has freedom of choice13 or, more generally, by the assumption that which specific measurements are actually performed is not governed by the HVs that govern the particles. OI is based on the assumption that, as it happens in deterministic models [i.e., when p(a, b∣λ, x, y) ∈ {0, 1}], if we would know λ, we would observe that p(a, b∣λ, x, y) = p(a∣λ, x, y)p(b∣λ, x, y)14. PI is grounded on the assumption that superluminal signalling between one party’s choice and the other party’s spacelike separated outcome is impossible10.
Existing experiments are inconclusive about which assumptions fail. As a consequence, possible explanations include HV theories with different degrees of “measurement dependence”12,14,15,16,17,18,19,20,21 (that may occur due to limitations to freedom of choice22,23 or to retrocausal influences24,25), different amounts of instantaneous “actions at a distance”26,27,28,29,30,31,32, and combinations thereof33. At least one of the four assumptions is false. But which one or which ones?11[pp. 124, 149, 96],34[p. 66]. The prevalent view is that advancing in the resolution of this problem is not possible “on purely physical grounds but it requires an act of metaphysical judgement”35. Here, we challenge this view and present two results. Result 1 shows that there are quantum correlations that cannot be simulated with any HV theory assuming OI but partial (as opposed to complete) measurement dependence (MD) or partial parameter dependence (PD). Result 2 shows that there are quantum correlations that cannot be simulated with any HV theory assuming MI, PI but partial outcome dependence (OD).
In Sec. II A, we introduce the standard ways to quantify MI, PI and OI. Result 1 is presented in Sec.II B, where we also describe an experiment to exclude HV theories with partial MD and PD. Result 2 is presented in Sec. II C, which includes the description of an experiment to exclude HV theories with partial OD. The consequences and applications of the results are discussed in Sec. III.
Results
Relaxing the assumptions
Quantifying measurement dependence
To quantify any lack of MI, and therefore to quantify MD, we have to take into account the distribution of x and y and, therefore, we have to consider the full distribution p(a, b, x, y) rather than only p(a, b∣x, y). The full distribution p(a, b, x, y) can be reproduced with an l-measurement dependent (l-MD) HV model36 if it can be reproduced with an HV model such that, for all x ∈ X, y ∈ Y, and for all λ,
If there are only two inputs per party, a value l = 1/4 implies that p(x, y∣λ) must be uniform. Therefore, in this case, p(a, b, x, y) can be reproduced with an HV model with MI in which there is no correlation between the hidden variables of the particles and the measurement settings. However, this is not the case for 0≤l < 1/4. We say that p(a, b, x, y) can be reproduced with an HV model with partial MD if there is an (l-MD) model for some l > 0. We say that p(a, b, x, y) can only be reproduced with an HV model with complete MD if p(a, b, x, y) cannot be reproduced with any (l-MD) model for any l > 0; the only possible HV models have p(x, y∣λ) = 0 for some pair of settings (x, y) and some λ. If there are only two inputs per party, any p(a, b, x, y) corresponding to any non-signaling correlation can be reproduced with an HV model with complete MD. The complete relaxation of MI using alternative ways of quantifying MD14,18 matches the above definition of complete MD (see also Supplementary Note1).
Quantifying parameter dependence
A correlation p(a, b∣x, y) can be reproduced with an (εA, εB)-parameter dependent [(εA, εB)-PD] HV model14 if it can be reproduced with an HV model such that, for all x, y, y′ (y, x, x′), and for all λ,
Therefore, p(a, b∣x, y) can be reproduced with an HV model with PI if, and only if, it can be reproduced with an (εA, εB)-PD HV model with εA = εB = 0. If not, we say that p(a, b∣x, y) can be reproduced with an HV model with partial PD if it can be reproduced with an (εA, εB)-PD HV model for some 0 < εA, εB < 1. Finally, p(a, b∣x, y) can only be reproduced with HV models with complete PD if p(a, b∣x, y) cannot be reproduced with any (εA, εB)-PD HV model for any εA, εB < 1. Any non-signaling correlation can be reproduced with HV models with complete PD.
Quantifying outcome dependence
A correlation p(a, b∣x, y) can be reproduced with a δ-outcome dependent (δ-OD) HV model14 if it can be reproduced with an HV model such that, for all x, y, a, a′, and for any λ,
Therefore, p(a, b∣x, y) can be reproduced with an HV model with OI if, and only if, it can be reproduced with a δ-OD HV model with δ = 0. We say that p(a, b∣x, y) can be reproduced with an HV model with partial OD if it can be reproduced with a δ-OD HV model with 0 < δ < 1. We say that p(a, b∣x, y) can only be reproduced with an HV model with complete OD if it cannot be reproduced with any δ-OD HV model for any δ < 1. Any non-signaling correlation can be reproduced with HV models with complete OD.
Result 1: Quantum correlations that cannot be simulated if there is arbitrarily small MI or PI
Consider the bipartite Bell experiment in which Alice and Bob have two measurement options x, y ∈ {0, 1}, each of them with 2N possible results which can be expressed as a string of N bits, a, b ∈ {(0, 0, …, 0), (0, 0, …, 1), …, (1, 1, …, 1)}. Suppose that Alice and Bob share the following 2N × 2N-dimensional entangled state:
where
with \(a=\frac{\sqrt{5}-1}{2}\), is a two-qubit state with the first qubit in Alice’s side and the second qubit in Bob’s side. Suppose that Alice’s and Bob’s measurements are of the form
where, here, the tensor product refers to the qubits in each observer’s system and the specific form of the factors is given by
where
with \(\left\vert \varphi \right\rangle=\frac{1}{\sqrt{1-{a}^{2}}}(\sqrt{1-2{a}^{2}}\left\vert 0\right\rangle -a\left\vert 1\right\rangle )\). That is, each of the 2N-outcome measurements can be seen as N (nonindependent) two-outcome measurements performed simultaneously on a 2N-dimensional quantum system. These state and measurements produce a correlation with the following properties:
for all a1, …, aN, b1, …, bN ∈ {0, 1}. Eq. (14a) indicates that, if the measurements are x = 0 for Alice and y = 1 for Bob, then, in the N-bit strings that Alice and Bob obtain as outputs cannot be one position where Alice has 0 and Bob has 1. Similarly, for Eqs. (14b) and (14c). These state and measurements are the ones needed for the parallelised version37 of the optimal version of the proof of Bell non-locality proposed by Hardy38.
Let us define
where ∨ is the logical OR.
Result 1 can be stated as follows: In any l-MD and (εA, εB)-PD HV model satisfying OI and Eqs. (14a), (14b) and (14c), for all l > 0 and all N,
The proof is in the Supplementary Note 2. Therefore, if εA < 1 and εB < 1, then \({p}_{H}^{N}\, < \,1\). In contrast, in quantum theory37, as N tends to infinity,
Consequently, for any l-MD and (εA, εB)-PD HV model with l > 0, εA < 1, εB < 1, satisfying OI, there is N such that quantum theory predicts a value for \({p}_{H}^{N}\) that cannot be simulated.
For example, Table 1 gives the values of ε = εA = εB that cannot be simulated if nature achieves the quantum value for \({p}_{H}^{N}\). Notice that the number of excluded HV models grows with N. As N tends to infinity, the only surviving HV models are those with ε = 1.
The correlations defined by Eqs. (10)–(13) are special: they define an extremal non-exposed point of the quantum set of correlations for the two-observer two-setting two-outcome Bell scenario39. Any other correlation with this property can also be used in the experiment. The full characterisation of these points is in40.
A natural question is what conditions a correlation must satisfy to allow for arbitrarily small MI and PI, and whether there are quantum correlations in Bell scenarios with finite number of inputs that allow for such relaxation. In the Supplementary Note 3, we show a necessary condition - the quantum correlation must necessarily lie on or be arbitrarily close to the nonsignaling boundary. We also illustrate by an explicit example that this condition is not sufficient. We leave as an open question whether there is a finite input-output quantum correlation that proves Result 1.
Experimental test to exclude HV theories with partial MD and PD
So far, we have identified a quantum correlation that cannot be simulated by any l-MD and (εA, εB)-PD HV model with l > 0, εA < 1, εB < 1, satisfying OI. This correlation is a point in the set of quantum correlations. The problem is that, due to experimental errors, an actual experiment will fail to exactly produce this point. Here, we reformulate Result 1 in a way that the existence of correlations that cannot be simulated by l-MD and (εA, εB)-PD HV models with l > 0, εA < 1, εB < 1, and satisfying OI, can be experimentally tested.
It can be proven (see Supplementary Note 4) that, for any l-MD and (εA, εB)-PD HV model with l > 0, εA < 1, εB < 1, satisfying OI, the following Bell-like inequality holds:
where
with
where \(\varepsilon=\max \{{\varepsilon }_{A},{\varepsilon }_{B}\}\), and
This means that, for any l-MD and (εA, εB)-PD HV model with l > 0, εA < 1, εB < 1, satisfying OI, for sufficiently large κ, the quantity \({I}_{\kappa }^{N}({p})\) is upper bounded by a value that is always smaller than 1. Furthermore, for fixed N, this bound approaches the bound for (16) when we take large values of κ and is therefore violated by the quantum state and measurements described earlier.
Result 2: Quantum correlations which cannot be simulated if there is arbitrarily small OI
Consider the bipartite Bell experiment in which Alice and Bob have M + 1 measurement options x, y ∈ {0, 1, …, M}, each of them with 2 possible results, a, b ∈ {0, 1}. Suppose that Alice and Bob share the following two-qubit entangled state:
where t ∈ [0, 1] is the value that maximises
Alice’s and Bob’s measurements are of the form \({A}_{a| x}=| {\pi }_{a| x}\left.\right\rangle \left\langle \right.{\pi }_{a| x}|\) and \({B}_{b| y}=| {\sigma }_{b| y}\left.\right\rangle \left\langle \right.{\sigma }_{b| y}|\), with
and
with
These state and measurements produce a correlation with the following properties:
and correspond to the optimal implementation of the “ladder” version of Hardy’s proof21,38,40.
Let us define
Result 2 can be formulated as follows: In any δ-OD HV model that satisfies MI, PI and Eq. (27),
where \(q=\frac{M+1}{2}\). The proof is provided in the Supplementary Note 5. Therefore, if δ < 1, it follows that \({p}_{H}^{M} < \frac{1}{2}\). In contrast, in quantum theory21,40, as M approaches infinity,
Consequently, for any HV model with MI, PI and δ-OD, with δ < 1, there is M such that quantum theory predicts a value for \({p}_{H}^{M}\) that cannot be simulated. In addition, it can be proven (see Supplementary Note 6) that the set of correlations produced by HV with MI, PI and complete OD is the set of nonsignaling correlations.
The above proof is based on the assumption that Eq. (27) hold. In an actual experiment, instead of the zeros Eq. (27), we will obtain small values. Once we have them, we can derive an optimal Bell-like inequality that will allows us to discard any HV model with δ-OD for some δ < 1.
Discussion
The results presented have consequences both for foundations and applications in quantum information processing, communication and computation. For foundations, our results bring us closer to the solution of a problem proposed by Shimony11[pp. 96, 124, 149]34[p. 66] and which can be formulated as follows: “One of these three premises [MI, PI and OI] must be false and it is important to locate the false one”11[p. 96]. If we assume that only one is false (and that it is the same one for all non-local quantum correlations), then
-
I.
If the assumption that fails is MI, Result 1 shows that, MI has to fail completely because there are quantum correlations that can only be explained with complete MD.
-
II.
If the assumption that fails is PI, Result 1 shows that, PI has to fail completely because the same correlations used in [I] can only be explained with complete PD.
-
III.
If the assumption that fails is OI, Result 2 shows that OI has to fail completely because there are quantum correlations that can only be explained with complete OD.
Each of these solutions to Shimony’s problem requires extra causal influences which are not needed if HVs do not exist. These extra causal influences are shown with non-black colours in Fig. 1a–c, respectively. The causal influences if HVs do not exist are shown in Fig. 1d.
In all diagrams, black arrows represent causal influences common to all possibilities. a Complete measurement dependence. It can occur in, essentially, two ways. The first is with complete superdeterminism without retrocausality. In this case, Alice and Bob do not have freedom of choice to choose the measurement settings, X and Y, respectively. Instead, the settings are determined by the distribution of the HVs in the past light cones of X and Y, represented by the lower node Λ. The causal influences between the lower Λ and X and Y are represented by violet continuous arrows. The second way complete MD can occur is with complete retrocausality with freedom of choice. In this case, Alice and Bob have freedom to choose the “nominal” measurement settings X and Y, but the actual measurements are determined by the distribution of the HVs in the future light cones of X and Y, represented by the upper node Λ. The causal influences between the upper Λ and X and Y are represented by violet dashed arrows. b Complete parameter dependence. X is decided by Alice and Y is decided by Bob. However, X does not only influence Alice’s measurement outcome, represented by A, but also Bob’s measurement outcome, represented by B, which is outside the light cone of X. This superluminal influence (or “action at a distance'') is represented by a red arrow. Similarly, Y does not only influence B, but also A. c Complete outcome dependence. X is decided by Alice and Y is decided by Bob. However, A and B are causally connected despite they are space-like separated. These superluminal influences are represented by blue arrows. d No hidden variables. X is decided freely by Alice and Y is decided freely by Bob. A is causally connected only to the quantum state, represented by Ψ, and X. Similarly, B is causally connected only to Ψ and Y.
More generally, our results allow us to experimentally narrow down the possible explanations of Bell non-locality and the whole quantum theory, since they allow to experimentally excluding large subsets of HV models that are not excluded by previous experiments. Specifically, in principle, any l-MD, (εA, εB)-PD HV model with l > 0, εA < 1, εB < 1, satisfying OI can be experimentally excluded. Similarly, any δ-OD HV model with δ < 1 and satisfying MI and PI can be, in principle, experimentally excluded. Still, the experiments cannot exclude HV models with complete MD22 or complete PD26,32 or complete OD.
Result 1 extends the observation in36 that there are quantum correlations that cannot be obtained from an l-MD HV model that satisfies OI and PI, for all values of l > 0. In36, the difference between quantum theory and the models with OI, PI and arbitrarily small MI is so small that any relaxation of PI makes the difference to vanish. In this respect, Result 1 makes testable the impossibility of HV models with partial MD and PD.
Result 2 is related to the observation in31 that there are quantum correlations that cannot be simulated with the assumptions of causal models (CM), MI, causal parameter independence (CPI) and the complete relaxation of causal outcome independence (COI). This observation is not made in the framework of the four assumptions of Bell’s theorem (HV, MI, PI, OI) but in the framework of causal models41. In general, neither HV and CM, nor PI and CPI, nor OI and COI, are equivalent.
In addition, Results 1 and 2 confirm that there is some interchangeability between MD and (PD+OD)42,43. However, our results go beyond that as they show that epsilon of each of MD and (PD+OD) is not enough: complete MD or complete PD or complete OD is needed.
One reason why it is important to exclude HV models with partial (but not complete) MD is that these models have been proposed to explain quantum correlations12,14,15,16,17,18,19,20,21. In addition, partial MD or, more precisely partial human’s free will, has been proposed in philosophy to resolve the conflict between the concept of an omniscient God and God’s commandment not to commit sin44.
One reason why it is important to exclude HV models with partial (but not complete) actions at a distance is that these models have been proposed to explain quantum correlations27,28,29,30,31,32. A second reason, which also applies to HV models with partial MD, is that excluding larger sets of HV models facilitates the discussion of the remaining models and, in particular, the discussion of the thermodynamics of the HV models45 that could not be discarded.
Our results are also of practical interest in quantum information processing, quantum communication and quantum computation. In the first place, for a general reason: the results show that quantum correlations do not only offer advantage with respect to local correlations, but also with respect to correlations assisted by partial instantaneous actions at a distance or even assuming the existence of partial constraints to freedom of choice or partial retrocausal influences. This can make a big difference in quantum computational advantage. For example, when mapping quantum non-local correlations into the circuit model, the advantage of quantum theory with respect to local HV theories translates into a non-oracular quantum advantage46,47. Our results show that there is also advantage with respect to non-local correlations with partial MD, PD and OD. This may translate into new forms of quantum computational advantage.
Another reason why our results are of practical interest is device-independent (DI) quantum information processing48,49. DI protocols for random number generation50, quantum key distribution48, state tomography51 and self-testing of quantum devices52 achieve advantage allowing users to monitor the performance of their devices irrespective of noise, imperfections, and lack of knowledge regarding the inner workings - the users simply treat their devices as black boxes with classical inputs and outputs. An obstacle for practical DI protocols is the experimentally challenging requirement of a Bell test with: (I) quantum devices being isolated from each other, (II) with the inputs being chosen with uniform randomness and (III) with the detection loophole53 closed. Experiments in different platforms54,55,56 allow for Bell tests with the detection loophole closed and high DI randomness generation rates. However, in these platforms, the quantum systems are very close, primarily to drive high entanglement generation rates via non-negligible coupling. The problem is that, precisely because the systems are close to one another, they can no longer be regarded as isolated in the sense needed for a Bell test. Sophisticated theoretical techniques have been devised to handle the issues of cross-talk and weak seeds separately. A Bell-like test allowing for arbitrary relaxation of MI and PI provides a simple and elegant solution to the problem of leakage of input information. A Bell-like test allowing for simultaneous relaxation of MI, PI and OI would allow DI randomness generation tolerating weak seeds and cross-talk. We hope that our results will stimulate research in these directions.
Data availability
No data sets were generated or analysed during the current study.
References
Born, M. Quantenmechanik der stoßvorgänge. Z. Physik 38, 803–827 (1926).
Bell, J. S. On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen paradox. Physics 1, 195–200 (1964).
Clauser, J. F., Horne, M. A., Shimony, A. & Holt, R. A. Proposed experiment to test local hidden-variable theories. Phys. Rev. Lett. 23, 880–884 (1969).
Einstein, A., Podolsky, B. & Rosen, N. Can quantum-mechanical description of physical reality be considered complete? Phys. Rev. 47, 777–780 (1935).
Freedman, S. J. & Clauser, J. F. Experimental test of local hidden-variable theories. Phys. Rev. Lett. 28, 938–941 (1972).
Aspect, A., Dalibard, J. & Roger, G. Experimental test of Bell’s inequalities using time-varying analyzers. Phys. Rev. Lett. 49, 1804–1807 (1982).
Hensen, B. et al. Loophole-free Bell inequality violation using electron spins separated by 1.3 kilometres. Nature 526, 682–686 (2015).
Giustina, M. et al. Significant-loophole-free test of bell’s theorem with entangled photons. Phys. Rev. Lett. 115, 250401 (2015).
Shalm, L. K. et al. Strong loophole-free test of local realism. Phys. Rev. Lett. 115, 250402 (2015).
Jarrett, J. P. On the physical significance of the locality conditions in the Bell arguments. Noûs 18, 569–589 (1984).
Shimony, A. Search for a Naturalistic World View. Volume II: Natural Science and Methaphysics (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK, 1993).
Hall, M. J. W. The significance of measurement independence for Bell inequalities and locality. In Asselmeyer-Maluga, T. (ed.) At the Frontier of Spacetime: Scalar-Tensor Theory, Bells Inequality, Machs Principle, Exotic Smoothness, vol. 183 of Fundamental Theories of Physics, 189-204 (Springer, Switzerland, 2016).
Bell, J. S., Shimony, A., Horne, M. A. & Clauser, J. F. An exchange on local beables. Dialectica 39, 85–110 (1985).
Hall, M. J. W. Relaxed Bell inequalities and Kochen-Specker theorems. Phys. Rev. A 84, 022102 (2011).
Colbeck, R. & Renner, R. Free randomness can be amplified. Nat. Phys. 8, 450–453 (2012).
Brandão, F. G. S. L. et al. Realistic noise-tolerant randomness amplification using finite number of devices. Nat. Commun. 7, 11345 (2016).
Hall, M. J. W. Complementary contributions of indeterminism and signaling to quantum correlations. Phys. Rev. A 82, 062117 (2010).
Barrett, J. & Gisin, N. How much measurement independence is needed to demonstrate nonlocality? Phys. Rev. Lett. 106, 100406 (2011).
Ramanathan, R. et al. Randomness amplification under minimal fundamental assumptions on the devices. Phys. Rev. Lett. 117, 230501 (2016).
Hall, M. J. W. & Branciard, C. Measurement-dependence cost for Bell nonlocality: Causal versus retrocausal models. Phys. Rev. A 102, 052228 (2020).
Ramanathan, R., Banacki, M. & Horodecki, P. No-signaling-proof randomness extraction from public weak sources. arXiv preprint arXiv:2108.08819 (2021).
Brans, C. Bell’s theorem does not eliminate fully causal hidden variables. Int. J. Theor. Phys. 27, 219–226 (1988).
’t Hooft, G. The Cellular Automaton Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics, vol. 185 298 of Fundamental Theories of Physics (Springer Cham, 2016).
Costa de Beauregard, O. A response to the argument directed by einstein, poldosky and rosen against the bohrian interpretation of quantum phenomena. C. R. Acad. Sci. 236, 1632–1634 (1953).
Donadi, S. & Hossenfelder, S. Toy model for local and deterministic wave-function collapse. Phys. Rev. A 106, 022212 (2022).
Bohm, D. A suggested interpretation of the quantum theory in terms of “hidden” variables. I. Phys. Rev. 85, 166–179 (1952).
Brassard, G., Cleve, R. & Tapp, A. Cost of exactly simulating quantum entanglement with classical communication. Phys. Rev. Lett. 83, 1874 (1999).
Bacon, D. & Toner, B. F. Bell inequalities with auxiliary communication. Phys. Rev. Lett. 90, 157904 (2003).
Pironio, S. Violations of Bell inequalities as lower bounds on the communication cost of nonlocal correlations. Phys. Rev. A 68, 062102 (2003).
Pawłowski, M., Kofler, J., Paterek, T., Seevinck, M. & Brukner, Č. Non-local setting and outcome information for violation of Bell’s inequality. New J. Phys. 12, 083051 (2010).
Ringbauer, M. et al. Experimental test of nonlocal causality. Sci. Adv. 2, e1600162 (2016).
Brask, J. B. & Chaves, R. Bell scenarios with communication. J. Phys. A: Math. Theor. 50, 094001 (2017).
Blasiak, P. Classical systems can be contextual too: Analogue of the mermin–peres square. Ann. Phys. 353, 326–339 (2015).
Shimony, A.Search for a Naturalistic World View. Volume I: Scientific Method and Epistemology (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK, 1993).
Polkinghorne, J. Physics and theology. Europhys. News 45 (2014).
Pütz, G., Rosset, D., Barnea, T. J., Liang, Y.-C. & Gisin, N. Arbitrarily small amount of measurement independence is sufficient to manifest quantum nonlocality. Phys. Rev. Lett. 113, 190402 (2014).
Mančinska, L. & Vidick, T. Unbounded entanglement in nonlocal games. Quantum Inf. Comput. 15, 1317–1332 (2015).
Hardy, L. Nonlocality for two particles without inequalities for almost all entangled states. Phys. Rev. Lett. 71, 1665–1668 (1993).
Goh, K. T. et al. Geometry of the set of quantum correlations. Phys. Rev. A 97, 022104 (2018).
Zhao, S., Ramanathan, R., Liu, Y. & Horodecki, P. Tilted Hardy paradoxes for device-independent randomness extraction. Quantum 7, 1114 (2023).
Wood, C. J. & Spekkens, R. W. The lesson of causal discovery algorithms for quantum correlations: causal explanations of Bell-inequality violations require fine-tuning. New J. Phys. 17, 033002 (2015).
Conway, J. H. & Kochen, S.The strong free will theorem, 443–454 (Cambridge University Press, 2011).
Blasiak, P., Pothos, E. M., Yearsley, J. M., Gallus, C. & Borsuk, E. Violations of locality and free choice are equivalent resources in Bell experiments. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 118, e2020569118 (2021).
Specker, E. Die Logik nicht gleichzeitig entscheidbarer Aussagen. Dialectica 14, 239–246 (1960).
Cabello, A., Gu, M., Gühne, O., Larsson, J.-A. & Wiesner, K. Thermodynamical cost of some interpretations of quantum theory. Phys. Rev. A 94, 052127 (2016).
Bravyi, S., Gosset, D. & König, R. Quantum advantage with shallow circuits. Science 362, 308–311 (2018).
Bravyi, S., Gosset, D., König, R. & Tomamichel, M. Quantum advantage with noisy shallow circuits. Nat. Phys. 16, 1040–1045 (2020).
Liu, Y. et al. Device-independent quantum random-number generation. Nature 562, 548–551 (2018).
Zhang, W. et al. A device-independent quantum key distribution system for distant users. Nature 607, 687–691 (2022).
Pironio, S. et al. Random numbers certified by Bell’s theorem. Nature 464, 1021–1024 (2010).
Mayers, D. & Yao, A. Self testing quantum apparatus. Quantum Info. Comput. 4, 273–286 (2004).
Magniez, F., Mayers, D., Mosca, M. & Ollivier, H. Self-testing of quantum circuits. In Bugliesi, M., Preneel, B., Sassone, V. & Wegener, I. (eds.) Automata, Languages and Programming, 72–83 (Springer Berlin Heidelberg, Berlin, Heidelberg, 2006).
Pearle, P. M. Hidden-variable example based upon data rejection. Phys. Rev. D 2, 1418–1425 (1970).
Rowe, M. A. et al. Experimental violation of a Bell’s inequality with efficient detection. Nature 409, 791–794 (2001).
Ansmann, M. et al. Violation of Bell’s inequality in Josephson phase qubits. Nature 461, 504–506 (2009).
Arute, F. et al. Quantum supremacy using a programmable superconducting processor. Nature 574, 505–510 (2019).
Acknowledgements
We thank Paweł Horodecki and Pedro Lauand for discussions and acknowledge support from the Early Career Scheme (ECS) (Grant No. 27210620), the General Research Fund (GRF) (Grant No. 17211122), the Research Impact Fund (RIF) Grant No. R7035-21), the MCINN/AEI project “New tools in quantum information and communication” (Project No. PID2020-113738GB-I00), and the Digital Horizon Europe project "Foundations of quantum computational advantage” (FoQaCiA) (Grant agreement No. 101070558).
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Contributions
C.V., R.R., and A.C. contributed equally to this work.
Corresponding authors
Ethics declarations
Competing interests
There are no competing interests.
Peer review
Peer review information
Nature Communications thanks the anonymous reviewer(s) for their contribution to the peer review of this work. A peer review file is available
Additional information
Publisher’s note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Supplementary information
Rights and permissions
Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License, which permits any non-commercial use, sharing, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if you modified the licensed material. You do not have permission under this licence to share adapted material derived from this article or parts of it. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article’s Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article’s Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/.
About this article
Cite this article
Vieira, C., Ramanathan, R. & Cabello, A. Test of the physical significance of Bell non-locality. Nat Commun 16, 4390 (2025). https://doi.org/10.1038/s41467-025-59247-7
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1038/s41467-025-59247-7